How can we trust the Bible if it's not inerrant?

Argue for and against Christianity

Moderator: Moderators

Post Reply
User avatar
otseng
Savant
Posts: 20745
Joined: Thu Jan 15, 2004 1:16 pm
Location: Atlanta, GA
Has thanked: 206 times
Been thanked: 355 times
Contact:

How can we trust the Bible if it's not inerrant?

Post #1

Post by otseng »

From the On the Bible being inerrant thread:
nobspeople wrote: Wed Sep 22, 2021 9:42 amHow can you trust something that's written about god that contradictory, contains errors and just plain wrong at times? Is there a logical way to do so, or do you just want it to be god's word so much that you overlook these things like happens so often through the history of christianity?
otseng wrote: Wed Sep 22, 2021 7:08 am The Bible can still be God's word, inspired, authoritative, and trustworthy without the need to believe in inerrancy.
For debate:
How can the Bible be considered authoritative and inspired without the need to believe in the doctrine of inerrancy?

While debating, do not simply state verses to say the Bible is inspired or trustworthy.

----------

Thread Milestones

User avatar
alexxcJRO
Guru
Posts: 1624
Joined: Wed Jun 29, 2016 4:54 am
Location: Cluj, Romania
Has thanked: 66 times
Been thanked: 215 times
Contact:

Re: Atheism and morality

Post #3361

Post by alexxcJRO »

otseng wrote: Fri Nov 24, 2023 7:33 am “The God of the Old Testament is arguably the most unpleasant character in all fiction: jealous and proud of it; a petty, unjust, unforgiving control-freak; a vindictive, bloodthirsty ethnic cleanser; a misogynistic, homophobic, racist, infanticidal, genocidal, filicidal, pestilential, megalomaniacal, sadomasochistic, capriciously malevolent bully.”
Yahweh is jealous:

“You shall not make for yourself a carved image, or any likeness of anything that is in heaven above, or that is in the earth beneath, or that is in the water under the earth. You shall not bow down to them or serve them, for I the Lord your God am a jealous God, visiting the iniquity of the fathers on the children to the third and the fourth generation of those who hate me, but showing steadfast love to thousands of those who love me and keep my commandments” (Exod. 20:4-6).

“For you shall worship no other god, for the Lord, whose name is Jealous, is a jealous God(Exod. 34:14).
“Phinehas the son of Eleazar, son of Aaron the priest, has turned back my wrath from the people of Israel, in that he was jealous with my jealousy among them, so that I did not consume the people of Israel in my jealousy(Num. 25:11).
“For the Lord your God is a consuming fire, a jealous God (Deut. 4:24).
“You shall not go after other gods, any of the gods of the peoples who are around you – for the Lord your God in your midst is a jealous God – lest the anger of the Lord your God be kindled against you, and he destroy you from off the face of the earth” (Deut. 6:14-15; cf. 29:20)
They stirred him to jealousy with strange gods; with abominations they provoked him to anger” (Deut. 32:16; cf. 32:21).
"But Joshua said to the people, 'You are not able to serve the Lord, for he is a holy God. He is a jealous God . . . " (Joshua 24:19).
"For they provoked him to anger with their high places; they moved him to jealousy with their idols"(Ps. 78:58).
"Therefore thus says the Lord God, 'Now I will restore the fortunes of Jacob and have mercy on the whole house of Israel, and I will be jealous for my holy name" (Ezek. 39:25).

Yahweh is bloodthirsty ethnic cleanser, genocidal, infanticidal, malevolent, unjust:

"16 However, in the cities of the nations the Lord your God is giving you as an inheritance, do not leave alive anything that breathes. 17 Completely destroy[a] them—the Hittites, Amorites, Canaanites, Perizzites, Hivites and Jebusites—as the Lord your God has commanded you. 18 Otherwise, they will teach you to follow all the detestable things they do in worshiping their gods, and you will sin against the Lord your God." (Deuteronomy 20:16-18)

"Now go, attack the Amalekites. Destroy everything that belongs to them as an offering to the Lord. Don’t let anything live. Put to death men and women, children and small babies. Kill the cattle and sheep, camels and donkeys.’”(1 Samuel 15:3)
“13 So God said to Noah, “I am going to put an end to all people, for the earth is filled with violence because of them. I am surely going to destroy both them and the earth. 14 So make yourself an ark of cypress[a] wood; make rooms in it and coat it with pitch inside and out. 15 This is how you are to build it: The ark is to be three hundred cubits long, fifty cubits wide and thirty cubits high.16 Make a roof for it, leaving below the roof an opening one cubit[c] high all around.[d] Put a door in the side of the ark and make lower, middle and upper decks. 17 I am going to bring floodwaters on the earth to destroy all life under the heavens, every creature that has the breath of life in it. Everything on earth will perish.”
(Genesis 6:13-17)
“The people of Samaria must bear their guilt,
because they have rebelled against their God.
They will fall by the sword;
their little ones will be dashed to the ground,
their pregnant women ripped open.
”[a]”
(Hosea 13:16)
"David Counts the Fighting Men
21 Satan rose up against Israel and incited David to take a census of Israel. 2 So David said to Joab and the commanders of the troops, “Go and count the Israelites from Beersheba to Dan. Then report back to me so that I may know how many there are.”
3 But Joab replied, “May the Lord multiply his troops a hundred times over. My lord the king, are they not all my lord’s subjects? Why does my lord want to do this? Why should he bring guilt on Israel?”
4 The king’s word, however, overruled Joab; so Joab left and went throughout Israel and then came back to Jerusalem. 5 Joab reported the number of the fighting men to David: In all Israel there were one million one hundred thousand men who could handle a sword, including four hundred and seventy thousand in Judah.
6 But Joab did not include Levi and Benjamin in the numbering, because the king’s command was repulsive to him. 7 This command was also evil in the sight of God; so he punished Israel.
8 Then David said to God, “I have sinned greatly by doing this. Now, I beg you, take away the guilt of your servant. I have done a very foolish thing.”
9 The Lord said to Gad, David’s seer, 10 “Go and tell David, ‘This is what the Lord says: I am giving you three options. Choose one of them for me to carry out against you.’”
11 So Gad went to David and said to him, “This is what the Lord says: ‘Take your choice: 12 three years of famine, three months of being swept away[a] before your enemies, with their swords overtaking you, or three days of the sword of the Lord—days of plague in the land, with the angel of the Lord ravaging every part of Israel.’ Now then, decide how I should answer the one who sent me.”
13 David said to Gad, “I am in deep distress. Let me fall into the hands of the Lord, for his mercy is very great; but do not let me fall into human hands.”
14 So the Lord sent a plague on Israel, and seventy thousand men of Israel fell dead. 15 And God sent an angel to destroy Jerusalem. But as the angel was doing so, the Lord saw it and relented concerning the disaster and said to the angel who was destroying the people, “Enough! Withdraw your hand.” The angel of the Lord was then standing at the threshing floor of Araunah b] the Jebusite.
16 David looked up and saw the angel of the Lord standing between heaven and earth, with a drawn sword in his hand extended over Jerusalem. Then David and the elders, clothed in sackcloth, fell facedown.
17 David said to God, “Was it not I who ordered the fighting men to be counted? I, the shepherd,[c] have sinned and done wrong. These are but sheep. What have they done? Lord my God, let your hand fall on me and my family, but do not let this plague remain on your people.”"
(1 Chronicles 21)

Yahweh is homophobic:
"If a man practices homosexuality, having sex with another man as with a woman, both men have
committed a detestable act. They must both be put to death, for they are guilty of a capital offense."(Leviticus 20:13)
"22 ‘Do not have sexual relations with a man as one does with a woman; that is detestable."(Leviticus 18:22)
“Don't you realize that those who do wrong will not inherit the Kingdom of God? Don't fool yourselves.
Those who indulge in sexual sin, or who worship idols, or commit adultery, or are male prostitutes, or
practice homosexuality, or are thieves, or greedy people, or drunkards, or are abusive, or cheat peoplenone of these will inherit the Kingdom of God. Some of you were once like that. But you were cleansed;
you were made holy; you were made right with God by calling on the name of the Lord Jesus Christ and
by the Spirit of our God.”(1 Corinthians 6:9-11)
"Now we know that the law is good, if one uses it lawfully, understanding this, that the law is not laid
down for the just but for the lawless and disobedient, for the ungodly and sinners, for the unholy and
profane, for those who strike their fathers and mothers, for murderers, the sexually immoral, men who
practice homosexuality, enslavers, liars, perjurers, and whatever else is contrary to sound doctrine ...."(1 Timothy 1:8-10)
otseng wrote: Fri Nov 24, 2023 7:33 am Richard Dawkins
A foundational assumption of skeptics to claim there are moral issues in the Old Testament is a standard exists to make ethical judgments that applies universally. To say God does or commands something morally wrong is asserting there is a standard that everyone, including God, ought to abide by. If they violate it, then it is morally wrong. But the problem for the skeptics is on what basis can they justify this universal ethical standard that everyone must abide by? And why do only humans have this sense of morality? Can animals do anything that are morally wrong?
According to Dawkins' naturalistic worldview, there is no evil and no good. It is all just pitiless indifference. There is no basis for atheists to assert the existence of any absolute ethical standard to judge if something is morally good or evil.
So, Dawkins contradicts himself by stating there is no evil and no good, yet judges the God of the Old Testament as being evil.
That morality does not exist in an atheistic worldview is also affirmed by atheist philosopher Joel Marks:
Philosopher Rüdiger Bittner says there is no moral ought:
There is no moral ought. For one thing, a morality of what one ought to do cannot account for the reason-giving force of moral judgements. For another, autonomy properly understood excludes our being subject to moral requirements. It is often argued that our common moral understanding is committed to there being things we ought to do—which is true, but does not decide the matter. That commitment itself lacks sufficient grounds, as among other things Aristotle’s example of a moral theory without ought shows. It is also argued that without moral requirements the ideas both of guilt and of blame will be lost—which is true again, but no cause for concern: we are better off without them.
https://academic.oup.com/book/46447/cha ... /407725795
Michael Ruse says morality is illusory:
Morality is a biological adaptation no less than are hands and feet and teeth... Considered as a rationally justifiable set of claims about an objective something, ethics is illusory. I appreciate that when somebody says, 'Love thy neighbor as thyself,' they think they are referring above and beyond themselves... Nevertheless... such reference is truly without foundation. Morality is just an aid to survival and reproduction... and any deeper meaning is illusory...
https://www.azquotes.com/quote/1140893
Philosopher Bertrand Russell says there is no moral standard:
"Outside human desires there is no moral standard."
https://iep.utm.edu/russ-eth/"

One can analyze concepts for consistency using logic, definitions, philosophy. The God of the Bible concept is not consistent.
According to logic, definitions, philosophy Yahweh is malevolent and evil. The bible portrays it as such.
The being does actions and behaves similar to other real or imagined evil and malevolent beings: Hitler, Joseph Stalin, Pol Pot, Nero, Genghis Khan, Darth Sidious, Frieza.
Any normal people would have not problem to admit the above list of characters is full of evil and malevolent beings.
Yet when it comes to religion we have to tap dance around philosophical concepts, definition and logic in a very dishonest way to somewhat arrive at a different conclusion because cognitive dissonance is a thing.
"It is forbidden to kill; therefore all murderers are punished unless they kill in large numbers and to the sound of trumpets."
"Properly read, the Bible is the most potent force for atheism ever conceived."
"God is a insignificant nobody. He is so unimportant that no one would even know he exists if evolution had not made possible for animals capable of abstract thought to exist and invent him"
"Two hands working can do more than a thousand clasped in prayer."

User avatar
otseng
Savant
Posts: 20745
Joined: Thu Jan 15, 2004 1:16 pm
Location: Atlanta, GA
Has thanked: 206 times
Been thanked: 355 times
Contact:

Re: Atheism and morality

Post #3362

Post by otseng »

Athetotheist wrote: Fri Nov 24, 2023 11:44 amThere are strong arguments to be made against the conclusions of the aforementioned atheists and philisophical amoralists, but that's not really why we're here.

If your purpose is to argue that Jehovah can't be judged by human standards, then the argument has to be extended to concede that no deity can be judged by human standards. Thus, Molech desiring children to be passed through the fire can't be denounced as wrong. Tezcatlipoca wanting human sacrifice to continue can't be denounced as wrong. Zeus seducing and impregnating young women can't be denounced as wrong. After all, they're gods.
alexxcJRO wrote: Fri Nov 24, 2023 1:18 pm One can analyze concepts for consistency using logic, definitions, philosophy. The God of the Bible concept is not consistent.
According to logic, definitions, philosophy Yahweh is malevolent and evil. The bible portrays it as such.
The being does actions and behaves similar to other real or imagined evil and malevolent beings: Hitler, Joseph Stalin, Pol Pot, Nero, Genghis Khan, Darth Sidious, Frieza.
Any normal people would have not problem to admit the above list of characters is full of evil and malevolent beings.
Yet when it comes to religion we have to tap dance around philosophical concepts, definition and logic in a very dishonest way to somewhat arrive at a different conclusion because cognitive dissonance is a thing.
You both did not address my argument. I'm arguing that from an atheistic/naturalistic perspective, the concept of morality does not exist, as backed by all the quotes I've provided. If one claims to be an atheist or humanist or secularist, morality is a meaningless term. There is no philosophical foundation to assert anything is evil (or even good) in such a worldview. And therefore it's meaningless to claim any god is evil or good.

If any atheist wants to claim God is evil, they must first justify their belief in morality. And they must also have a very strong argument if they are going to go against Dawkins, Marks, Bittner, Ruse, and Russell.

Athetotheist
Prodigy
Posts: 3087
Joined: Sat Nov 02, 2019 5:24 pm
Has thanked: 19 times
Been thanked: 555 times

Re: Atheism and morality

Post #3363

Post by Athetotheist »

[Replying to otseng in post #3362
If any atheist wants to claim God is evil, they must first justify their belief in morality. And they must also have a very strong argument if they are going to go against Dawkins, Marks, Bittner, Ruse, and Russell.
This argument doesn't apply to me since I'm not an atheist.

User avatar
otseng
Savant
Posts: 20745
Joined: Thu Jan 15, 2004 1:16 pm
Location: Atlanta, GA
Has thanked: 206 times
Been thanked: 355 times
Contact:

Re: Atheism and morality

Post #3364

Post by otseng »

Athetotheist wrote: Sat Nov 25, 2023 9:32 am [Replying to otseng in post #3362
If any atheist wants to claim God is evil, they must first justify their belief in morality. And they must also have a very strong argument if they are going to go against Dawkins, Marks, Bittner, Ruse, and Russell.
This argument doesn't apply to me since I'm not an atheist.
What worldview would you claim to have?
Would you agree atheists have no justification for objective morality to exist?

User avatar
otseng
Savant
Posts: 20745
Joined: Thu Jan 15, 2004 1:16 pm
Location: Atlanta, GA
Has thanked: 206 times
Been thanked: 355 times
Contact:

Ronald Lindsay - How Morality Has the Objectivity that Matters - Without God

Post #3365

Post by otseng »

One attempt to argue objective morality exists from an atheistic perspective is by Ronald Lindsay.
The thesis of this essay is that morality is not objective in the same way that statements of empirically verifiable facts are objective, yet morality is objective in the ways that matter: moral judgments are not arbitrary; we can have genuine disagreements about moral issues; people can be mistaken in their moral beliefs; and facts about the world are relevant to and inform our moral judgments. In other words, morality is not “subjective” as that term is usually interpreted. Moral judgments are not equivalent to descriptive statements about the world—factual assertions about cars, cats, and cabbages—but neither are they merely expressions of personal preferences.

This thesis has obvious importance to our understanding of morality. Moreover, this thesis has special relevance to humanists and other nonreligious people, because one of the most frequently made arguments against atheism is that it is incompatible with the position that morality is objective and that rejecting the objectivity of morality would have unacceptable consequences.
https://secularhumanism.org/2014/07/con ... thout-god/
Sure, some individual atheists can be relied upon to act morally, but, as political commentator Michael Gerson put it, “Atheists can be good people; they just have no objective way to judge the conduct of those who are not.” In other words, without God, atheists cannot explain how there are objective moral truths, and without objective moral truths, atheists have no grounds for saying anything is morally right or wrong. We atheists might act appropriately, but we cannot rationally justify our actions; nor can we criticize those who fail to act appropriately.
Yes, I agree with that.
Furthermore, this contention that God is required for morality to be objective has become the new weapon of choice for those wishing to argue for the existence of God.
Though this can be true, this is not relevant to the thesis. It is the atheists who claim God is evil, so they must first demonstrate moral claims are justifiable.
For these reasons—and also because we want a firm grounding for morality ourselves—it is incumbent upon humanists, and secular ethicists generally, to address squarely the contentions that without God there is no objectivity in morality and that this situation would be something dreadful.
Yes.
The problem is that most try to do this by arguing that morality is objective in a way similar to the way in which ordinary descriptive statements are objective. The better argument is that morality is neither objective nor subjective as those terms are commonly understood.
Lindsay tacitly acknowledges atheists have not been able to provide an adequate solution.

Here he seems to want to change the definitions. Let's see what he actually means. But first he addresses the common arguments by atheists.

Argument from well-being:
Or, if one wants to approach the issue from the other direction, well-being is a good thing, and, all other things being equal, people want to have well-being. The argument will then proceed by using this foundation to argue that we have a moral obligation to avoid inflicting pain or to increase well-being. But this will not do. Granted, pain is “bad” in a nonmoral sense, and people don’t want it, but to say that inflicting pain on someone is presumptively morally bad implies we have some justification for saying that this action is morally bad, not just that it’s unwanted. From where does this moral obligation derive and how do we detect it?
He cites Derek Parfit:
Derek Parfit, an Oxford scholar whom some regard as one of the most brilliant philosophers of our time (and I so regard him), recently produced a massive work on ethics titled On What Matters. This two-volume work covers a lot of ground, but one of its main claims is that morality is objective, and we can and do know moral truths but not because moral judgments describe some fact. Indeed, moral judgments do not describe anything in the external world, nor do they refer to our own feelings. There are no mystical moral or normative entities. Nonetheless, moral judgments express objective truths. Parfit’s solution? Ethics is analogous to mathematics. There are mathematical truths even though, on Parfit’s view, there are no such things as an ideal equation 2 + 2 = 4 existing somewhere in Plato’s heaven. Similarly, we have objectively valid moral reasons for not inflicting pain gratuitously even though there are no mystical moral entities to which we make reference when we declare, “Inflicting pain gratuitously is morally wrong.” To quote Parfit, “Like numbers and logical truths … normative properties and truths have no ontological status” (On What Matters, vol. 2, p. 487).

Parfit’s proposed solution is ingenious because it avoids the troublesome issues presented when we tie moral judgments to facts about the world (or facts about our feelings). However, ingenuity does not ensure that a theory is right. Parfit provides no adequate explanation of how we know ethical truths, other than offering numerous examples where he maintains we clearly have a decisive reason for doing X rather than Y. In other words, at the end of the day he falls back on something such as intuition, with the main difference between his theory and other theories being that his intuitions do not reference anything that exists; instead they capture an abstract truth.
In other words, Parfit also does not provide a justification for morality.
So secular attempts to provide an objective foundation for morality have been … well, less than successful. Does this imply we are logically required to embrace nihilism?

No. Let me suggest we need to back up and look at morality afresh. The whole notion that morality must be either entirely subjective or objective in some way comparable to factual (or in Parfit’s case, mathematical) truths is based on a misguided understanding of morality. It’s based on a picture of morality in which morality serves functions similar to factual descriptions (or mathematical theorems). We need to discard that picture. Let’s clear our minds and start anew.
He explicitly acknowledges secularist attempts have been less than successful in justifying morality.

I don't think we need to "start anew", but let's see what he has to say.
So, if we are starting from the ground up, let’s ask basic questions. Why should we have morality?

Broadly speaking, morality appears to serve these related purposes: it creates stability, provides security, ameliorates harmful conditions, fosters trust, and facilitates cooperation in achieving shared and complementary goals. In other words, morality enables us to live together and, while doing so, to improve the conditions under which we live.

Multiply this example millions of times, and you get a sense of the numerous transactions among people that allow a peaceful, stable, prospering society to emerge. You also can imagine how conditions would deteriorate if moral norms were not followed.
No disagreement with this.
In rejecting the proposition that moral judgments are equivalent to factual statements about the world, I am not endorsing the proposition that moral judgments are subjective. A subjective statement is still a descriptive statement that is determined to be true by reference to facts. It’s simply a descriptive statement referring to facts about our inner states—our desires, our sentiments—as opposed to something in the world. To claim that moral judgments are subjective is to claim that they are true or false based on how a particular person feels. That’s not how most of us regard moral judgments.
He stated above he is not claiming morality is subjective.
The reality is that there is a core set of moral norms that almost all humans accept.
Yes, and another question is why is this true?

I don't see a clear explanation proposed by him to justify morality. His point seems to center on subjectivity vs objectivity:
We can see now how morality has the type of objectivity that matters. If we regard morality as a set of practices that has something like the functions I described, then not just any norm is acceptable as a moral norm.
Yes, we all agree morality is objective.
Because of our common human condition, morality is not arbitrary; nor is it subjective in any pernicious sense.
Again states that morality is not subjective.
There is no single simple principle that governs morality. Yes, we want to encourage people to be virtuous—that is, to be kind, courageous, and trustworthy—but to what end?
We recognize that morality is objective, but it is interesting we cannot fully define what is morality, but we do all have a similar inner sense of what it is.
A second important objection to my argument is that I have not explained how it is that moral norms are binding on us. Even if we accept that there is a common morality, why must we follow these norms?
Yes, this is a key question.
The combination of our evolutionary inheritance and the moral training most of us receive disposes us to act morally.
No, evolutionary inheritance has nothing to do with morality. The most obvious counter to this is morality does not exist outside of humans. Do plants and animals even have the concept of morality?
There is no mystical intuition of “the moral law” that inexorably forces someone to accept the institution of morality. Nor is there any set of reasons whose irresistible logic compels a person to behave morally. Put another way, it is not irrational to reject the institution of morality altogether. One can coherently and consistently prefer what one regards as one’s own self-interest to doing the morally appropriate thing.
Yes, in an atheistic worldview, this would be correct.
That said, there is no guarantee that people will not make this choice. But notice that bringing God into the picture doesn’t change anything. People can make the decision to reject morality even if they think God has promulgated our shared moral norms.
True. But the issue is not how one behaves, but how one ought to behave.
You may say: “But what they did was objectively wrong”—and an atheist can’t say this. As you have admitted, there is nothing outside the institution of morality to validate this institution, so the obligations of morality are not really binding.” If one means by “objectively wrong” something that conforms to a standard of wrongness that exists completely independently of the human condition and our moral practices, then, correct, an atheist might not use “objectively wrong” in this sense. (Some ethicists who are atheists might, as I have already discussed.) But so what?
Here, Lindsay affirms an atheist cannot say anything is objectively wrong.
First, as indicated by the Euthyphro argument, the notion that God could provide such an external standard is highly questionable.
At least from a theist point of view, there is a logical justification for a moral standard.
Second, and more important, what is lost by acknowledging that morality is a wholly human phenomenon that arose to respond to the need to influence behavior so people can live together in peace? I would argue that nothing is lost, except some confused notions about morality that we would do well to discard.
Because as he acknowledges, "One can coherently and consistently prefer what one regards as one’s own self-interest to doing the morally appropriate thing." No behavior is objectively right or wrong. People can do whatever they want and there is nothing that people ought to do.
At this point, the believer might protest, “But there has to be something more than that. Morality is not just a human institution.” Well, what is this something more? Why is it not enough to tell the wrongdoer that everyone condemns him because what he or she did violated our accepted norms, which are essential to our ability to live together in peace?
Morality is more than just accepted norms. Two hundred years ago, slavery was an accepted norm. Today, abortion is an accepted norm.

Though people do want to live in peace, there is no "oughtness" that everyone should live in peace. Also one person's peace can result in another person's lack of peace. Kim Jong Un wants peace. But are the people of North Korea living in a moral country? And on what basis can anyone say their leader is evil?
What some believers (and, again, some secular ethicists) appear to want is some further fact, something that will make them more comfortable in claiming that moral norms are authoritative and binding. Somehow it is not sufficient that a norm prohibiting the gratuitous affliction of violence reduces pain and suffering and allows us to live together in peace, and has, therefore, been adopted by all human societies. No; for the believer there has to be something else. A moral norm must be grounded in something other than its beneficial effects for humans and human communities. The statement that “it was wrong for Kim to hit Stephanie” must pick out some mystical property that constitutes “wrongness.” For the believer, this further fact is usually identified as a command from God, but as we have already established, God’s commands cannot be regarded as imposing moral obligations unless we already possess a sense of right and wrong independent of his commands.
There has to be some justification for the universality of this ethical intuition. Yes, I grant it is not solely from commandments from any religious text. We seem to intuitively understand what is ethical since all religions share similar standards. Even atheists agree that murder is wrong.

And it cannot be from evolution, since morality has nothing to do with evolution. There is no "oughtness" in evolution. There is only what actually happens, not how things should happen. Animals kill each other. There is no requirement that animals should not kill each other.
However, the whole world has moved away from the gold standard with no ill effects.
Yes, there are ill effects, in particular inflation, which all fiat monetary systems have undergone.
Why didn’t our economic systems collapse or become wildly unstable? Because currency doesn’t need anything outside of the economic system itself to provide it with value.
There is no fiat monetary system that has withstood the test of time. However, gold has never been worthless in human history.
Similarly, moral norms represent the value found in living together. There is no need to base our moral norms on something outside of our relationships. Moral norms are effective in fostering collaboration and cooperation and in improving our conditions, and there is no need to refer to a mystical entity, a gold bar, or God to conclude that we should encourage everyone to abide by common moral norms.
A fiat monetary system is actually a good analogy for an atheistic view of morality. Atheistic morality is based on what people for a certain time and place believe, like all fiat currencies. It cannot apply for all people for all of history, unlike gold. So, atheistic morality is not objective, but subjective.
In conclusion, the claim that we need God to provide morality with objectivity does not withstand analysis.
It is not really the burden of his thesis to disprove theistic morality, but to defend objective atheistic morality. And he doesn't really offer any good justification for an objective atheistic morality.
To begin with, God would not be able to provide objectivity, as the argument from Euthyphro demonstrates.
From the Jewish perspective, the Euthyphro dilemma does not exist:
Jonathan Sacks wrote, "In Judaism, the Euthyphro dilemma does not exist." Jewish philosophers Avi Sagi and Daniel Statman criticized the Euthyphro dilemma as "misleading" because "it is not exhaustive": it leaves out a third option, namely that God "acts only out of His nature."
https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Euthyphro_dilemma
Moreover, morality is neither objective nor subjective in the way that statements of fact are said to be objective or subjective; nor is that type of objectivity really our concern.
It is either objective or subjective. There is no third option. It is either morality is dependent on the standards of an individual or society for a certain place and time (subjective) or it applies to everyone regardless of place and time (objective).
Our legitimate concern is that we don’t want people feeling free “to do their own thing,” that is, we don’t want morality to be merely a reflection of someone’s personal desires.
Right, we all agree we cannot live by subjective morality.
To the extent that intersubjective validity is required for morality, it is provided by the fact that, in relevant respects, the circumstances under which humans live have remained roughly the same. We have vulnerabilities and needs similar to those of people who lived in ancient times and medieval times, and to those of people who live today in other parts of the world. The obligation to tell the truth will persist as long as humans need to rely on communications from each other. The obligation to assist those who are in need of food and water will persist as long as humans need hydration and nutrition to sustain themselves. The obligation not to maim someone will persist as long as humans cannot spontaneously heal wounds and regrow body parts. The obligation not to kill someone will persist as long as we lack the power of reanimation. In its essentials, the human condition has not changed much, and it is the circumstances under which we live that influence the content of our norms, not divine commands. Morality is a human institution serving human needs, and the norms of the common morality will persist as long as there are humans around.
Yes, humans throughout history all share an innate sense of morality. So, objective morality exists. But the important question is where does that come from and why do we have it? He has no answer for this except that it's not from God. And actually he never even claims to address these fundamental questions, but only claims to address the objectivity of morality. We all agree objective morality exists, so not even sure how his article contributes to anything.

He stated, "one of the most frequently made arguments against atheism is that it is incompatible with the position that morality is objective." The issue is not can atheists be objectivity moral. Yes, they can be. The issue is on what basis can they justify their objective morality? It's like Christians can believe in God. But skeptics would counter this by asking on what basis do Christians believe in God? What are the justifications for such a belief? Is it just blind faith or are there arguments with evidence to support it? And for atheistic objective morality, Lindsay does not offer any justification for his belief in objective morality.

Athetotheist
Prodigy
Posts: 3087
Joined: Sat Nov 02, 2019 5:24 pm
Has thanked: 19 times
Been thanked: 555 times

Re: Atheism and morality

Post #3366

Post by Athetotheist »

[Replying to otseng in post #3364
What worldview would you claim to have?
First, let me ask you this: Are you claiming that only Christians have an objective basis for morality?

Would you agree atheists have no justification for objective morality to exist?
I'm not here to argue about atheists. I'm here to argue about the veracity of the Bible.

User avatar
alexxcJRO
Guru
Posts: 1624
Joined: Wed Jun 29, 2016 4:54 am
Location: Cluj, Romania
Has thanked: 66 times
Been thanked: 215 times
Contact:

Re: Atheism and morality

Post #3367

Post by alexxcJRO »

otseng wrote: Sat Nov 25, 2023 5:30 am
alexxcJRO wrote: Fri Nov 24, 2023 1:18 pm One can analyze concepts for consistency using logic, definitions, philosophy. The God of the Bible concept is not consistent.
According to logic, definitions, philosophy Yahweh is malevolent and evil. The bible portrays it as such.
The being does actions and behaves similar to other real or imagined evil and malevolent beings: Hitler, Joseph Stalin, Pol Pot, Nero, Genghis Khan, Darth Sidious, Frieza.
Any normal people would have not problem to admit the above list of characters is full of evil and malevolent beings.
Yet when it comes to religion we have to tap dance around philosophical concepts, definition and logic in a very dishonest way to somewhat arrive at a different conclusion because cognitive dissonance is a thing.
You both did not address my argument. I'm arguing that from an atheistic/naturalistic perspective, the concept of morality does not exist, as backed by all the quotes I've provided. If one claims to be an atheist or humanist or secularist, morality is a meaningless term. There is no philosophical foundation to assert anything is evil (or even good) in such a worldview. And therefore it's meaningless to claim any god is evil or good.

If any atheist wants to claim God is evil, they must first justify their belief in morality. And they must also have a very strong argument if they are going to go against Dawkins, Marks, Bittner, Ruse, and Russell.

1. But saying Yahweh does not exists does not entail as saying no God exist. A indifferent deist god could exist and would be consistent with all the suffering and malevolence present.

2. I can claim Hitler is evil, malevolent per usage of definitions and logical concepts. The same way I claim Yahweh is evil, malevolent per usage of definitions and logical concepts.

Q: The question is why are worshiping such a being which is clearly portraited in the Bible as malevolent and evil?

3. Yahweh god concept is not consistent for on one hand it is claimed to be omni-being, wise, just, loving, benevolent and on the other hand its actions convey it as being evil, malevolent, jealous, unjust, unwise, petty, genocidal, infanticidal, tribal, homophobic.
Ergo pointing to non-existence.

4.
Morality evolved because of natural selection.

Groups, pack, tribes that were more altruistic, that showed more cohesion, sympathy and empathy and cooperation were more likely to survive and find food. Groups were psychopathy was prevalent and showed mostly individual selfishness were less likely to survive.

We have an objective mechanism leading to a morality that is independent of religious propaganda or societal influence.

Evolution -> Mirror neurons -> Affective Empathy.

As a result of this mirroring process =affective empathy we humans(except psychopaths who have a innate problem involving the affective empathy) have developed intrinsically a sense of morality) mostly guided by the Golden Rule or law of reciprocity which is the principle of treating others as one would wish to be treated oneself.

It is a fact that when you see children, women being raped, tortured or killed; when you see the face of someone experiencing intense fear/pain/suffering your mirror neurons fire and the affective empathy process is triggered. You empathize with these people for you put yourself in their shoes aka the mirroring process and because you would not want to be raped, tortured, killed(your existence to be stopped, because of the survival instinct) you instinctively find these actions abhorrent.

Our intrinsic "Morality" is tied to Affective Empathy.

Enjoy! 8-)
"It is forbidden to kill; therefore all murderers are punished unless they kill in large numbers and to the sound of trumpets."
"Properly read, the Bible is the most potent force for atheism ever conceived."
"God is a insignificant nobody. He is so unimportant that no one would even know he exists if evolution had not made possible for animals capable of abstract thought to exist and invent him"
"Two hands working can do more than a thousand clasped in prayer."

User avatar
otseng
Savant
Posts: 20745
Joined: Thu Jan 15, 2004 1:16 pm
Location: Atlanta, GA
Has thanked: 206 times
Been thanked: 355 times
Contact:

Re: Atheism and morality

Post #3368

Post by otseng »

Athetotheist wrote: Sun Nov 26, 2023 10:17 am [Replying to otseng in post #3364
What worldview would you claim to have?
First, let me ask you this: Are you claiming that only Christians have an objective basis for morality?
No, I do not claim that.

User avatar
otseng
Savant
Posts: 20745
Joined: Thu Jan 15, 2004 1:16 pm
Location: Atlanta, GA
Has thanked: 206 times
Been thanked: 355 times
Contact:

Re: Atheism and morality

Post #3369

Post by otseng »

alexxcJRO wrote: Sun Nov 26, 2023 11:46 am 1. But saying Yahweh does not exists does not entail as saying no God exist. A indifferent deist god could exist and would be consistent with all the suffering and malevolence present.
Sure. We can discuss the problem of pain and suffering after the current discussion on God being evil.
2. I can claim Hitler is evil, malevolent per usage of definitions and logical concepts. The same way I claim Yahweh is evil, malevolent per usage of definitions and logical concepts.
Sure. But the issue is on what basis can atheists objectively call anything evil, whether it is God or Hitler?
Q: The question is why are worshiping such a being which is clearly portraited in the Bible as malevolent and evil?
This question is more a question of ethics rather than an existence issue. As a matter of fact, it implies God must exist to ask such a question.
3. Yahweh god concept is not consistent for on one hand it is claimed to be omni-being, wise, just, loving, benevolent and on the other hand its actions convey it as being evil, malevolent, jealous, unjust, unwise, petty, genocidal, infanticidal, tribal, homophobic.
Ergo pointing to non-existence.
No, it doesn't point to the non-existence of Yahweh. At most, it would only point to the non-existence of the God with the attributes that you perceive to exist. And even if God has all those attributes you described, it can just be a capricious God.
Morality evolved because of natural selection.
Yes, this is widely claimed by atheists. I'll post more about this in separate posts.
Groups, pack, tribes that were more altruistic, that showed more cohesion, sympathy and empathy and cooperation were more likely to survive and find food. Groups were psychopathy was prevalent and showed mostly individual selfishness were less likely to survive.

We have an objective mechanism leading to a morality that is independent of religious propaganda or societal influence.

Evolution -> Mirror neurons -> Affective Empathy.
No, just because a set of animals is "altruistic" or "empathetic" does not logically lead to humans being objectively moral.
It is a fact that when you see children, women being raped, tortured or killed; when you see the face of someone experiencing intense fear/pain/suffering your mirror neurons fire and the affective empathy process is triggered.
Yes, it is a fact in humans. But when animals kill and eat other weak and young animals, are they doing anything morally wrong?

User avatar
otseng
Savant
Posts: 20745
Joined: Thu Jan 15, 2004 1:16 pm
Location: Atlanta, GA
Has thanked: 206 times
Been thanked: 355 times
Contact:

Morality and Evolutionary Biology

Post #3370

Post by otseng »

There has been a push by evolutionists to claim evolutionary biology can explain morality. The article "Morality and Evolutionary Biology" in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy discusses this:
“Perhaps [biologists] can eventually do what philosophers have never managed, and explain moral behavior in an intellectually satisfying way.” These passages epitomize a growing theme in the popular and scientific media, echoing claims made forty years ago with the emergence of sociobiology, when E.O. Wilson suggested that “the time has come for ethics to be removed temporarily from the hands of the philosophers and biologicized”
https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/morality-biology/

Perhaps philosophers have not been able to explain the origin of morality. But this has never been a problem for theists. What we generally find is almost all philosophical questions can be addressed from a Judeo-Christian perspective. Whereas if you throw out God and the Bible, people cannot resolve basic philosophical questions even after thousands of years. But, this can be for a latter debate.

Evolution is really the only scientific tool atheists can use to explain morality. But does it adequately explain it?
When it comes to morality, the most basic issue concerns our capacity for normative guidance: our ability to be motivated by norms of behavior and feeling through judgments about how people ought to act and respond in various circumstances.
Agreed.
it is an empirical fact about human beings that we make moral judgments, have certain feelings and behave in certain ways, and it is natural for the sciences to seek causal explanations for such phenomena.
I agree morality is an empirical fact.
At the same time, however, it is a very complex matter—and one often neglected outside of philosophy—how such empirical, explanatory projects are related to the very different sets of questions and projects pursued by philosophers when they inquire into the nature and source of morality.
Yes, it is a complex topic.
Moral philosophers tend to focus on questions about the justification of moral claims, the existence and grounds of moral truths, and what morality requires of us. These are very different from the empirical questions pursued in the sciences, but how we answer each set of questions may have implications for how we should answer the other.

Progress in this area will not be made either by doing moral philosophy in isolation from the sciences or by taking morality out of the hands of philosophers and looking to scientific inquiry in isolation.
Yes, evolutionary biologists need to also understand the philosophical issues if they are to address morality adequately.

It presents three broad evolutionary approaches to morality:
A. Descriptive Evolutionary Ethics: appeals to evolutionary theory in the scientific explanation of the origins of certain human capacities, tendencies, or patterns of thought, feeling and behavior.

B. Prescriptive Evolutionary Ethics: appeals to evolutionary theory in justifying or undermining certain normative ethical claims or theories.

C. Evolutionary Metaethics: appeals to evolutionary theory in supporting or undermining various metaethical theories.
Since (A) is purely descriptive and only describes things, there is no obvious justifications for the positions (B) and (C) since they are philosophical in nature.
Importantly, there are no simple or straightforward moves from the scientific projects in A to the philosophical projects in B or C.
It notes there are two senses of morality:
A. The Empirical Sense of ‘Morality’

Here ‘morality’ refers, as noted earlier, to a certain set of empirical phenomena, such as the observed capacity of human beings to make normative judgments, or the tendency to have certain sentiments such as sympathy or guilt or blame, or certain ‘intuitions’ about fairness or violence.

B. The Normative Sense of ‘Morality’

When we use ‘morality’ in the normative sense, it is meant to refer to however it is we ought to live, i.e., to a set of norms that ought to be adopted and followed.
Empirical morality (A) is how humans act. Normative morality (B) is how humans ought to act.

Though evolution attempts to account for morality, there is no clear linkage between adaptation and moral development:
It is uncontroversial that there will be evolutionary explanations of some sort for the very general capacities and tendencies in A and B: we are evolved creatures, and our psychological capacities, like other complex capacities, are outcomes of evolutionary processes. But this does not by itself settle whether these capacities and tendencies are themselves adaptations, having evolved through natural selection because of their adaptive effects.
It is only uncontroversial because evolution is the only possible scientific explanation atheists have.

Altruism is commonly presented in moral evolutionary development:
Many discussions of morality and evolutionary biology focus largely on the issue of altruistic feeling and behavior. This can be confusing because in addition to psychological altruism there is also biological altruism, which is found in many species. (See Kitcher 2011, part I, for a comprehensive discussion.) Psychological altruism involves caring about others’ welfare and deliberately benefiting them for their own sake, with no restriction on the type of benefit involved. By contrast, biological altruism has nothing essentially to do with intentions or motives, and it pertains only to ‘benefits’ to others that increase their reproductive fitness (boosting their genetic contribution to future generations).
Psychological altruism is motivated by intentions and motives. Biological altruism is motivated by reproductive fitness.

I think psychological altruism is more relevant to morality because morality requires intention and motives. And it admits this area is highly speculative.
This area of inquiry remains largely speculative, since it is one thing to develop models for how psychological altruism could in principle evolve, and quite another to show convincingly that a given form of natural selection has in fact played the relevant role in actual human evolutionary history.
It presents one theory of psychological altruism:
Kitcher (2006a,b; 2011) has proposed a three-stage account of the evolution of morality. It begins with the evolution of an early but fragile form of psychological altruism among hominins in the context of “coalition games” in mixed adult groups.
It presents an entirely hypothetical scenario with three stages of development of human morality.
Human beings have a strong, emotionally-laden sense of basic fairness, resentment of cheaters, and a desire that they be punished, all of which finds expression in both cultural norms and individual moral judgments. You might experience such feelings if you’ve been the victim of a scam, morally condemning the perpetrators.
Agreed.
And some of these psychological traits may have analogues in other species. For example, Sarah Brosnan and Frans de Waal (2014) argue that “evidence indicates that [inequity aversion, i.e., negative reactions to unequal rewards for similar tasks] is widespread in cooperative species under many circumstances”--though some have disputed this and offered alternative hypotheses to explain the behavior, based on further research (Engelmann, Clift, Herrmann, and Tomasello 2017).[5] In the simplest case, an animal protests when it sees a companion receive a superior reward for a similar task, as in a well-known study with brown capuchin monkeys, though similar effects have now been observed even in non-primates, such as dogs and crows. In the more complex case, chimpanzees sometimes react negatively to inequity even where they are the ones receiving the greater reward.
However, aren't these counter-examples to altruism?
the proper question is not in the first instance what caused that judgment to occur, but what reasons the person had for making it—for thinking it to be true. It is those reasons that typically constitute an explanation of the judgment. They explain by bringing out what the person took (rightly or wrongly) to be the justification for the belief in question—the considerations showing the belief likely to be true. All of this complicates the explanatory project in relation to the thoughts, feelings and actions of rational agents.
Right. What is missing in evolutionary theories is the judgment that is involved in actions performed. If there is no judgment involved, how can an action be considered to be right or wrong? If something does action A, how can it be asserted it ought to have done action B if it could not judge between A and B to perform? Why would it be morally wrong to have done A if there was no decision actually made?

Morality requires autonomy for any judgment to be made:
Few would deny the autonomy assumption altogether. To do so in the name of providing alternative evolutionary causal explanations of our beliefs would risk self-defeat: for if we lack the relevant intellectual autonomy across the board, then even the biologist’s beliefs about evolutionary biology and its implications would just be attributable to such biological causes, rather than to reasons that provide real warrant for such beliefs within a rational framework with truth-tracking integrity.
Morality requires reasoning to make a decision:
This brings us back to moral judgment. As with M, P and S, people typically have reasons for their moral judgments, and whether or not we agree with them, we typically take those reasons to explain why they believe what they do.
And how do we know anything (particularly animals) are able to exercise autonomous reflection?
One potential lesson from evolutionary biology, however, is that even if the autonomy assumption equally applies in principle to the sphere of moral judgment, it may be a mistake just to assume that most moral judgment and behavior is in fact a result of the exercise of such autonomous reflection, reasoning and judgment. The autonomy assumption, after all, says only that we have the capacity for relevantly autonomous reflection and judgment; it does not imply that we always exercise it. Perhaps the human capacity for autonomous thinking is exercised only in some cases, while in others the process that leads to moral belief is largely influenced by evolved psychological dispositions, such as emotional adaptations.
Even in the case of humans, autonomous reflection might not be involved. But, I would argue even if reflection was not involved, it can still be judged to be moral or not. Someone might shoot a gun at a wall without thinking it would kill anyone. But if a person on the other side of the wall was killed, he would still be considered guilty.
But the controversies are as much ongoing philosophical ones as scientific ones, and it is therefore unlikely that scientific results will settle them. Science will plainly not settle, for example, whether or not there are moral truths; and if there are, they will likely play an explanatory role with regard to at least some of our moral beliefs—something we will miss if we approach these issues from an exclusively scientific point of view.
Yes, science will not settle the question of moral truths. So, the best science can offer is the "Modest Evolutionary Explanatory Thesis":
The Modest Evolutionary Explanatory Thesis: evolutionary forces may adequately explain certain capacities and tendencies associated with moral thinking, feeling and behavior, and may explain or partially explain some of the content of our moral thought, feeling and behavior, insofar as it is influenced (individually or via influences on cultural development) by those tendencies.
To state that science can explain morality is, at best, hyperbole.

As for normative morality, evolutionary theory is lacking for an explanation:
Even philosophers sympathetic to ethical naturalism (the view that moral facts are themselves natural facts of some sort) have typically been wary of attempts to derive conclusions about morality in the normative sense from facts about evolutionary history. This is especially so when they are clear (unlike Spencer) about the principles governing Darwinian evolution through natural selection. From the fact that a certain trait is an adaptation, which evolved through natural selection by virtue of its positive feedback effects on germ-line replication of the alleles that generate the trait, nothing at all seems to follow about whether it is morally good or right, or something we ought to embrace and foster. Certain dispositions may be present in us for good evolutionary reasons without any implication that these traits benefit us, or are moral virtues or produce behaviors that are morally right.

It is hard to see how such evolutionary facts can possibly have normative authority or force for a rational agent.

This suggests that ethics, like mathematics, is an autonomous subject in the sense that it has its own “internal standards of justification and criticism”, such that its conclusions cannot be justified by other forms of inquiry such as evolutionary biology.

Normative ethical conclusions are justified through first-order ethical reflection and argument, just as mathematical propositions are justified through mathematical reasoning, rather than through learning more about our evolutionary past or about what is happening in our brains when we engage in these forms of reasoning.
There are only two main arguments for morality - special creation and evolution:
Rachels takes such an approach against the common belief that human beings have a special moral dignity that is much higher than the status enjoyed by non-human animals. Such a belief has traditionally been rooted in the idea that we are separate from other living things, having been created specially in the image of God and endowed with souls, giving us a special moral status. If evolutionary theory is true, however, then this support is undermined: since Homo sapiens evolved from other species, there is no sharp biological separation between Homo sapiens and the rest of the living world; there is instead a continuum through evolutionary history, with no species created separately, in a divine image, or infused with special souls. Thus, those who have based their beliefs about the speical moral status of human beings on a creationist picture have a problem: that picture is false, and the true picture does nothing to support such a view.
Another problem for evolutionists is arguing there is nothing different with humans compared to all other animals (biological evolution), yet it also has something different (morality). But in special creation, there is no such conflict because it asserts humans are in a different class than all other animals, both from a biological origin and the ability to make moral judgments.

It affirms evolution theory cannot account for normative morality:
As noted earlier, however, the normative goals themselves will not have been set for us by evolutionary biology or psychology.
Can evolution provide answers to the existence and nature of morality?
While evolutionary facts may do little to illuminate the content of morality in the normative sense (apart from shedding light on morally relevant facts), they are sometimes thought to tell us something about the existence and nature of morality in the normative sense.
Evolution, at its core, is correlated with biological fitness, not moral oughtness:
But natural selection shaped those dispositions simply according to which variations best contributed to the biological fitness of our hominin ancestors, rather than in ways that would be expected to track independent moral truths as such, even if they existed. That is, natural selection rewarded moral belief-forming dispositions that yielded whatever moral beliefs led to behaviors that caused hunter-gatherers to out-reproduce their peers and propagate their genes more effectively, regardless of whether or not these beliefs happened accurately to represent a realm of independent moral truths.
Evolution not being able to account for objective morality has been recognized since Darwin:
It is worth noting that the appeal to evolution to support general skeptical worries about ethics is not in fact new: it goes all the back to Darwin himself. Consider the following provocative, fanciful reflection (later echoed closely by E.O. Wilson 1978, 204–206), which at least suggests a skeptical argument closely related to the debunking arguments examined above:

It may be well first to premise that I do not wish to maintain that any strictly social animal, if its intellectual faculties were to become as active and as highly developed as in man, would acquire exactly the same moral sense as ours. In the same manner as various animals have some sense of beauty, though they admire widely different objects, so they might have a sense of right and wrong, though led by it to follow widely different lines of conduct. If, for instance, to take an extreme case, men were reared under precisely the same conditions as hive-bees, there can hardly be a doubt that our unmarried females would, like the worker-bees, think it a sacred duty to kill their brothers, and mothers would strive to kill their fertile daughters; and no one would think of interfering. Nevertheless the bee, or any other social animal, would in our supposed case gain, as it appears to me, some feeling of right and wrong, or a conscience (Darwin 1871, 73).
At best, evolution can only account for subjective morality, but not objective morality.
The argument at least suggested by this passage is that our moral sense, which generates our moral beliefs, has the shape and content it has because of the contingencies of human ecology; had creatures with a very different ecology, such as bees, come to be rational, they would thus have developed a very different moral sense suitable to their ecology. But then which of these very different moral senses could be expected reliably to track moral truths (if they exist)? The answer seems to be: neither (unless we simply relativize moral truths to various possible ecologies, taking such truths to reduce to facts about effective genetic propagation—though as we saw in section 3, such a move has little moral plausibility). For moral senses are contingent products of particular ecologies in a way that cannot be expected to track independent and stable moral truths. We and the hypothetical rational bees will thus have very different moral outlooks, each of which is explicable in terms of our respective ecologies and will seem quite natural to those who occupy the relevant ecology (while the other’s outlook will seem bizarre), but neither of which seems to have any claim to be a reliable guide to moral truth (as usually conceived).

Post Reply