After reading all that I concede that deductive and inductive validity are two entirely different subjects, but however I had nothing of deduction in my mind when I put the two categories. Also, thanks for the logic lesson, I learnt a lot

.
You're also right that soundness implies validity.
But,
Adamoriens wrote:I'm not sure that it should even be called "inductive validity", since the failure of an argument to raise its conclusion above 50% probability may not have its cause in a fallacy. But I can't think of an example where this would be the case, so go ahead and use the latter term.
Adamoriens wrote:Fair enough. I retract my claim that purely inductive arguments cannot have formal fallacies, in light of wikipedia:
Wikipedia wrote:...an argument can contain a formal fallacy even if the argument is not a deductive one; for instance an inductive argument that incorrectly applies principles of probability or causality can be said to commit a formal fallacy.
Let me see, if an inductive argument doesn't contain a fallacy, there's a possibility that the truth of the premises will lead (not entail, though) the truth of the conclusion. That is, there's a chance, be it over or below 50%.
But, if it contains one, which is what until here I meant by "invalid induction" (how do we call it, fallacious induction?), then such possibility is 0%. That is, even if the conclusion turns out to be true, the argument cannot even "lead" to this truth, it will simply "have happened", and therefore the argument will be void.
While you still seem to hold that religious faith through induction falls in the first type, I'll still try to defend that it falls in the second. Also, remember that "religious claims" in this sense won't mean the existence of a cross, or the existence of a tomb, but only those claims only believable by believers in theism.
You provided this definition:
An inductive argument is an argument in which it is thought that the premises provide reasons supporting the probable truth of the conclusion.
And let's use it to determine if it's an induction or some wild fallacy:
Adamoriens from Wikipedia wrote: 1. I always hang pictures on nails.
2. Therefore: All pictures hang from nails.
I can recognize here a generalization, the author inferred the status of all pictures from his experience with this kind of objects. The conclusion is possible from the premise (not "probable", since this is really weak and probable means "likely"). This would qualify for me as a weak induction.
Adamoriens wrote:In kind, I offer:
1. Many of the incidental historical details of the Bible have been confirmed by secular archaeology.
2. The Bible includes reports of miracles as if they were history.
3. Therefore, it is likely that the reports of miracles are also historical details.
4. If the reports of miracles are historical details, then Christianity is true.
5. Christianity is probably true.
As you can see, this is actually a far better argument than the example from wiki, and it also includes a deductive step (4) which may or may not contain a formal fallacy.
There are a whole bunch of things I can remark here. First, this are two arguments and not one. The first concludes that miracles are historically reported, and the second concludes that Christianity is most likely true (though I'm not sure a conclusion can be just "likely"). Let's analyze the first one:
1. Historical details of the Bible are true.
2. Miracles are historical details (according to the Bible.)*
Therefore, miracles are true (since they're historical and not legendary).
[You can add "most likely" to the conclusion but that will just make it "most likely" false.]
I don't think this qualifies as an induction, since if the premises were true (which both are), the conclusion would be true (*), I would put it as a deduction or maybe syllogism (I don't know exactly). But, there's a minor detail which renders the conclusion unsound though it's valid. If we count the parenthesis in the premise 2., this turns out to be
circular logic. Why are miracles
true historical details - because the Bible says so. Why is the Bible accurate? Because Christianity is true - which if I remember well, was your final conclusion.
Now let's go on with the second:
1. Miracles are most likely true (from 1)
2. If miracles are true, then Christianity is true.
Therefore, Christianity is most likely true.
This is plain deduction, and a valid one. The soundness of the final premise will depend on the soundness of 1. (already discussed) since I think 2. is already defined to be true.
I can't see how this qualifies as an "induction". On the other hand, I've seen this kind of induction:
1. Everything has a conscious maker.
2. Plants are (or have the qualities of) things.
Therefore, plants have a conscious maker.
(Though this might actually seem a deduction, it's indeed an extrapolation, though you're open to question it.)
What makes this logic invalid or fallacious? It's the circularity in naming (a fallacy), since the argument is almost a tautology. (Though I'm not sure if it could still be called valid, it's as valid as "A is red because A is red".) When I first put it I was thinking of something like "inductive arguments which
can be true (sound) and induction which is necessarily unsound". This is necessarily unsound, because:
1. presupposes the conclusion (if plants are to be taken as "everything").
2. presupposes the conclusion (if plants are not to be taken as "everything").
That is, I implicitly acknowledge the nature of things to plants (or attribute a similar property) in order to conclude that they have a property I entailed to the premises. Even if the statement "plants have a maker" were sound, the argument's conclusion is unsound because it also falls into
circular reasoning. Just like if "A is red" were in fact true, my above argument would not be sound logical reasoning for it.
Adamoriens wrote:Darn, I saved that mega-post as a draft. I want my ten tokens. Neutral
Ouch

PM a mod?